In cognitive science, one example of a problem of underdetermination is the ‘poverty of the stimulus’ faced by children learning their first language. In this case, the given information is the sample of language to which a child is exposed. The problem is that this information is in principle consistent with an infinity of different natural grammars, only one of which is correct.
Problems of underdetermination are
often found in the study of visual perception.
The information provided directly to our eyes (the proximal stimulus) is
actually consistent with an infinite number of different scene interpretations
(models of the world). Only one of these
interpretations is correct.
We do not experience problems of
underdetermination, suggesting that the human mind has mechanisms that eliminate
incorrect conclusions, delivering only the correct result. It seems that the mind provides additional
information that serves as a ‘filter’ that only lets correct conclusions
through, as shown in the figure below, which assumes that ‘Conclusion 2’ is correct:
Similarly, perception researchers
argue that visual problems of underdetermination are solved by adding required
knowledge of the world. For some, this
knowledge is innate: the visual system is wired in such a way that certain
general properties (neighbouring points in a scene will have similar color,
depth, motion, and so on) are true. For
others – the New Look theorists – this knowledge is general knowledge of the
world, which provides context that can be used to solve the problem of
underdetermination. For the New Look,
seeing is literally a kind of thinking.
Cognitive scientists are not the
only scholars who face problems of underdetermination. Music theorists are often concerned with analyzing
musical scores by assigning chord labels to configurations of notes. However, different theorists may assign
radically different chords to the same score, a classic example of
underdetermination. David Damschroder,
in his 2008 book Thinking About Harmony,
observes that “analysts guided by contrasting basic principles may offer wildly
divergent views concerning a chord’s root; or, the same chord may be
interpreted in different ways depending upon its context. … A chord may in
certain contexts be understood as an incomplete or modified representative of
some other chord” (p. 17).
Ukulele players constantly face
this kind of underdetermination. When
learning their instrument they soon realize that a single finger configuration
on the fret board can have more than one chord name! Two of the many examples of this are
illustrated in the figure below. For the
first pair (F6 and Dm7), note that the interpretation of the chord’s name
depends upon which ukulele string is assumed to provide the chord’s root note
(the string associated with the number 1 at the bottom of each chord diagram).
The solution to this problem is to
play a subset of a chord’s notes, four notes that are sufficient to
provide the musical sense of the chord even when the other notes are
absent. One example of this is the
second pairing of chords in the figure directly above. If one assumes that one of the strings
provides the chord’s root, then the chord could be named as Bm7♭5. However, if one
assumes that the root is not one of the notes that is actually played, one can
interpret the same set of four notes as a chord extension, G9.
A ukulele player cannot avoid
chord underdetermination. How can they
cope with interpreting music, or deciding upon chord names as they compose
their own music?
My suggestion is to endorse the
position of the New Look theory of visual perception, and rely upon context
supplied by musical knowledge. Consider
the three chord progression provided in the figure below. From the information given above, it would be
completely correct to label the first chord as being F6, and the second chord
as being Bm7♭5. However, it is difficult to come up with a
basic musical context and key in which these chord labels make sense.
This raises an additional
interesting question: when one hears a chord progression, is their experience
of the chords affected by the context that they adopt? Do F6 and Dm7 actually sound like different
chords in different contexts, even though they are played in exactly the same
way on the ukulele? The New Look
theorists hypothesized that experience is indeed altered by the contexts,
beliefs, and expectations that we bring into perception.
References
Damschroder, D. (2008). Thinking
About Harmony. Cambridge University
Press. Cambridge, UK.